logo

54 pages 1 hour read

David Brooks

The Second Mountain

Nonfiction | Book | Adult | Published in 2019

A modern alternative to SparkNotes and CliffsNotes, SuperSummary offers high-quality Study Guides with detailed chapter summaries and analysis of major themes, characters, and more.

Introduction and Part 1, Chapters 1-4Chapter Summaries & Analyses

Part 1: “The Two Mountains”

Introduction Summary

Brooks opens with a brief description of those who “radiate joy” (xi). Such people, who have deeply held commitments to others and who feel delight in vocational dedication to these commitments are an inspiration for The Second Mountain. According to Brooks, these joyful people have often led a life with a “two-mountain shape” (xi). The concept of the second mountain and the person who climbs to its metaphorical peak structures the entire book; it is the book’s primary concept.

Brooks writes that on the first mountain a person is busy becoming an individual, creating and building an ego through independent realization of personal goals. Continuing the metaphor, Brooks writes that between the first and second mountains is a valley. The valley is a “season of suffering” in which some people are radically transformed (xiii). These people learn, through their struggles in this period of suffering, that they are more than the ego-identity they’ve created for themselves: “There is another layer of them they have been neglecting, a substrate where the dark wounds, and the most powerful yearnings live” (xii). While some people fall to pieces in the valley, others find themselves and begin their assent up the second mountain. The second mountain is defined not by the development of an ego-identity but rather its transcendence through other-centered ethics of care. On the second mountain, Brooks writes, “They see familiar things with new eyes. They are finally able to love their neighbor as themselves, not as a slogan but a practical reality” (xii).

For Brooks, the ascent to second-mountain personhood involves rebellion against the “ego ideal” and mainstream culture (xiii). Mainstream culture glorifies consumption and individual freedom, which buttresses the values of the ego ideal. The second-mountain person rejects these and journeys toward a new way of being with others. As Brooks writes, “It’s not about self anymore; it’s about a summons” (xiv). Brooks makes frequent use of examples, including that of Abraham Lincoln, who suffers assaults to personal (and presidential) dignity because of his other-centered moral goal of saving the union. For Lincoln, as for all who are on a second-mountain journey, the “ultimate appeal” is to something transcendent of the self (xvi). Second-mountain people feel moral joy in their pursuits, which is more than the experiential pleasures afforded on the first mountain.

Brooks then explains the plan and outline of the book. He writes that the book is about establishing a renewed sense of wholeness after the dissolution of this wholeness on the first mountain. It is about reconnection, community, and the process through which people develop wisdom over the course of a life of service. Brooks explains the importance of making deep and lasting commitments, especially in four domains: vocation, family, philosophy/faith, and community. Part of Brooks’s reason for writing the book is an outgrowth of his sense of the limitations of The Road to Character, his previous book of moral philosophy. Brooks writes that since the publication of that book he has dealt with life-changing circumstances that have afforded him an updated and enriched perspective on life. The Second Mountain is tasked with philosophically articulating this perspectival shift.

Brooks discusses the difference between happiness and joy. Whereas happiness is about the fulfillment of something pleasing to the ego-self, joy is discovered in the transcendence of the self in commitments to others. He then discusses six distinct “levels” of joy: physical joy, collective effervescence, emotional joy, spiritual joy, transcendent joy, and moral joy. Each form of joy is distinct from mere happiness. They are also hierarchically related; moral joy, in lieu of its relative permanence, is the zenith of joy. Brooks also stresses the value of transcendent and spiritual joy, especially in a culture wherein they are taboo. He discusses the elevation of moral joy and the fact that greater moral feeling can be developed through the formation of habits that are other-centered. Brooks writes that observation of moral exemplars should reveal that such people do not lead easy lives but often voluntarily take on heavy burdens. They live their lives at maximum capacity in service to others. He discusses a project he initiated in 2018 called Weave, the goal of which is to bring attention to “people who are doing the grassroots work of community building and relationship repair” (xxxii). He then reiterates that joy is an expression of a life well lived, an indication that one is on the right path up the second mountain.

Chapter 1 Summary: “Moral Ecologies”

In Chapter 1, “Moral Ecologies,” Brooks discusses his time as a TV pundit working for Jim Lehrer at PBS NewsHour. According to Brooks, Lehrer’s character helped establish a valuable moral ecology at the station. A moral ecology is a space/milieu in which particular virtues are expressed and expected. It is a “system of belief and behavior” that can be both individual and collective (4). Brooks discusses the moral ecology of the United States before the 1960s in which individuals sought value as part of a larger social organization, whether that be a corporation, church, or political party. “The ethos,” Brooks writes of this moral ecology, “nurtured the sort of rich, community life that many people pine for today” (5). He often refers to this as the “We’re All in This Together” ecology (4). Despite this, Brooks discusses the flaws in this moral ecology and makes use of a story from John Steinbeck’s Travels with Charlie to reinforce his point.

Due to the pressures of this moral ecology and its tendency to crush the value of the individual, a period of social turmoil emerged in the 1960s that radically restructured the moral ecology of the United States. He calls this new moral position the “I’m Free to Be Myself” ecology (7). It is inside this moral ecology, Brooks believes, that modern culture still resides. This ecology, which served as a legitimate and necessary correction to the flaws of the previous moral ecology, has outlived its usefulness and is now causing more harm than good. Brooks thinks that contemporary America is in the midst of another restructuring of its moral framework, putting the country in a crisis mode. He believes that the moral restructuring of a society is not the product of politicians but rather “moral activists and cultural pioneers” (8). “Those who shape the manners and mores,” he writes, “are the true legislators of mankind—they wield the greatest power and influence” (8).

The “I’m Free to Be Myself” ecology emphasizes the value of authenticity, personal liberty, and individual autonomy. As such, he writes, it is about the emancipation of the individual from oppressive group norms and expectations. He notes that it has both right and left-wing variants, which reveals its sweeping, fundamental restructuring of American life. Brooks believes that while the emergence of this moral ecology in the 1960s was “an absolutely necessary cultural revolution,” it has outlived its value. Problems with the central values of this ecology include the privatization of meaning, the “dream” of total freedom, and “the centrality of accomplishment” (11). Care for the self and its correspondent ego-ideal is at the center of this moral framework. This must be transcended for the second mountain. The hyper-individualism of such a society also makes its members overly susceptible to tribalism, which inculcates a very dangerous “us vs. them” mentality. Brooks concludes Chapter 1 by noting that society has overcorrected for the moral ecology of pre-1960s America. The situation, he writes, “makes it difficult to be good—to fulfill the deep human desires for love and connection” (13).

Chapter 2 Summary: “The Instagram Life”

In Chapter 2, “The Instagram Life,” Brooks criticizes some of the fundamental tenets of the “I’m Free to Be Myself” ideology. He frames this around the commencement address, an event in which a successful person of an older generation tells young people about the road to success, their futures, etc. He writes that “We use these speeches to pass along the dominant values of our age,” but the values of the present age turn out to be nothing more than “great empty boxes” (14). In other words, telling young people that they are free to make their own decisions, that life is awash in possibility, and that all they have to do is pursue their authentic selves, is no better than cutting them loose without direction or assistance. He writes:

You will notice that our answers take all the difficulties of living in your twenties and make them worse. The graduates are in limbo, and we give them uncertainty. They want to know why they should do this as opposed to that. And we have nothing to say except, Figure it out yourself based on no criteria beyond yourself. They are floundering in a formless desert. Not only do we not give them a compass, we take a bucket of sand and throw it all over their heads! (15).

The results of this useless advice and ideological disposition, Brooks believes, is aimlessness and terrible difficulty for young people. He believes there is a deep disparity between extremely structured childhoods and totally unsupervised young adulthood. He notes the severe underemployment and unemployment rates amongst recent college graduates and that half of these young people do not have any life goals or sexual partners. He then borrows Soren Kierkegaard’s concept of the “aesthetic life” to critique the adventurer mindset of some young people. Such youths judge their lives by aesthetic criteria and attempt to collect exciting and interesting experiences. This, according to Brooks, is a perfectly fine way to start one’s twenties, but it is no way to live a life, which is much more fulfilling when it is dedicated to deep commitments. “The problem,” he writes, “is that the person in the aesthetic phase sees life as possibilities to be experienced and not projects to be fulfilled or ideals to be lived out” (18). He ends the chapter by using the metaphor of a river of freedom to make his point. Young people need to cross the river of freedom to make it to the other side, at which point they will establish committed settlements. Adventurous “Freedom” is a useful temporary stage in life, but it is not a satisfying conclusion. 

Chapter 3 Summary: “The Insecure Overachiever”

Chapter 3 is about a different kind of recent college graduate: the “Insecure Overachiever.” He refers to these people as pragmatists, and he is equally suspicious of their futures. The utilitarian and pragmatic young person seeks to achieve at a very high rate and often works hard inside established institutions to do so. Unfortunately, in Brooks’s view, their pragmatic work addiction does not save these people from existential meaninglessness. It may be that this work-obsessed attitude can effectively distract people from emotional and spiritual malaise, but it cannot fix it. These people participate in a meritocracy, which provides the most meritorious individual with great individual rewards. The problem is that such a system turns everyone into a mass of competing individuals; it does not establish community relations. He notices a rising problem he terms “acedia.” Acedia is a life that is void of strong emotional attachments and depth of soul. “The person living in acedia,” Brooks writes, “may have a job and a family, but he is not entirely grabbed by his own life. His heart is over there, but his life is over here” (24). The possibility of living in and through one’s whole heart is abandoned. Externally, in the eyes of society, such a person is living a very good life. Internally, the soul has been deeply dampened.

Chapter 4 Summary: “The Valley”

Chapter 4, “The Valley,” is a turning point in Part 1. After discussing moral ecologies, the specific form of moral ethos present in modern American culture, and the two main life paths young people take when indoctrinated in this ethos, Brooks finally turns to the next layer of the fundamental metaphor: the valley between the two mountains. He opens the chapter with a long discussion of the life of acclaimed Russian novelist Leo Tolstoy. Tolstoy was incredibly successful and climbed a higher first mountain than almost anyone. After a life-changing experience, during which Tolstoy witnessed an execution, he changed his attitude to life, focusing solely on the pursuit of the second mountain. This life-changing experience, though, first shook him deeply, sending him into the “valley” of despair and heartache before the ascent up the second mountain. Many of us, Brooks believes, will undergo similar periods of suffering during which the pursuit up the first mountain of the ego ideal no longer seems valuable. This leads to a sort of existential crisis.

The “telos crisis” is a specific form of existential crisis during which people lose sense of the purpose of their lives (30). With David Foster Wallace, Brooks notes that this is caused by “moral directionlessness” (31). Not only can individuals, like Tolstoy, fall into the valley of moral despair, but entire societies can too. Still critical of modern American culture, Brooks writes, “The grand narrative of individual emancipation left us with what some have called ‘the great disembedding’” (31). This is the disentangling of closely-knit communities and norms. Brooks makes note of Simon May’s statement that love is “ontological rootedness” (31).

Brooks proceeds to discuss several specific aspects of this crisis, including loneliness. He notes that many Americans report being “chronically lonely,” and that deaths from suicide and opioids, which he mutually attributes to despair, are at historic highs. He even notes that the average American lifespan declined for a few years, from 2015-2018. He believes that growing levels of distrust and tribalism are also factors of the crisis, as well as a crisis of meaning, noting that many people have seemed to have “lost faith in faith” (34). He concludes the chapter with a discussion of suffering. Brooks is adamant of the view that periods of intense individual and social suffering are potentially also periods of radical transformation, capable of producing stronger and wiser people. The growth that can be extracted from protracted periods of suffering (by some individuals) is the result of a recognition that we need one another, that ego-generated goals are ultimately of little value, and (perhaps paradoxically) the understanding of the need for an intense sense of gratitude.

Introduction and Chapters 1-4 Analysis

The introduction is the most essential part of the book since Brooks discusses the impetus for the project, its crucial moral themes, and outlines how a moral life can be practically implemented. In short, The Second Mountain is about two fundamentally separate approaches to the good life: the “first mountain” and the “second mountain” approach. This dichotomy structures the entire book but is essentially schematized in the introduction and developed in Part 1. Whereas the first mountain is characterized by an egoism directed at the fulfillment of personal goals, the second mountain is, conversely, about community

Brooks writes, “This is ultimately a book about renewal, how things that are divided and alienated can find new wholeness” (xvii). As a work on renewal, Brooks indicates his intention that the book work on both the individual and the social level. The social ethos, or moral ecology, has created a society of isolated individuals working in competition for the ascendancy of personal, individual merits and values. Individuals are isolated from one another, creating a lived experience of alienation from community. The turn to the second mountain, on both the social and cultural level, in its endless work toward a more collaborative and communitarian standard of life, is an attempt to reintegrate individuals and families into a larger social fabric. The goal, as Brooks sees it, will not only increase social bonds but will subsequently make individual life more fulfilling. The best way to aim at personal happiness is in this sense not to aim at it at all but to instead direct all one’s energies toward other people, projects, and God. Brooks goes so far as to criticize the pursuit of happiness as an intrinsically good end. The fundamental distinction is between two emotional states, happiness and joy: “Happiness is what we aim for on the first mountain. Joy is a by-product of living on the second mountain” (xxiv). Joy, as we will see later, is a more powerful and altogether different affective state than happiness. He continues:

I now think good character is a byproduct of giving yourself away. You love things that are worthy of love. You surrender to a community or cause, make promises to other people, build a thick jungle of loving attachments, lose yourself in the daily act of serving others as they lose themselves I the daily acts of serving you. Character is a good thing to have, and there’s a lot to be learned on the road to character. But there’s a better thing to have—moral joy. And that serenity arrives as you come closer to embodying perfect love (xx).

In short, Brooks is advocating for people to explicitly and consciously orient themselves around their highest possible callings: the committed life and the moral joy that results therefrom. In line with this is an ongoing criticism of American culture insofar as it serves to isolate and distract us. This will be consistently developed throughout the book and comprises the fundamental theme of The Problems of American Culture in Brooks’s work.

To help illustrate this theme, Brooks cites poll information on mystical experiences, which are consistently considered to be among the most profound and impactful individual moments of a person’s life. The Gallup poll indicates not only the surprising pervasiveness of mystical experiences among Americans but also the simultaneous feeling of social taboo on the public discussion of these experiences. This reveals, for Brooks, that American culture is toxically antithetical to core elements of personhood, spirituality, etc.

Brooks believes that individual essences are mutable, elevated, or degraded in response to habits. Moral habits, centered on committed action for the benefit of others, alter an individual’s essence, making him/her more susceptible to an ethos of moral joy. In this regard, Brooks seems indebted to Aristotle, the father of virtue ethics. Aristotle’s ethics, which focus on attentive habit formation toward the cultivation of a virtuous soul, is also oriented around the fundamental value of something akin to joy, which we may term excellence or flourishing. In concert with the aforementioned dichotomy between happiness and joy, we may note that joy is a byproduct of a virtuous moral life, not the aim of such a life. Aristotelean virtue ethics is a clear and present, if unspoken, influence throughout much of Brooks’s moral project in The Second Mountain and creates the basis for Brooks’s theme of Personal Commitments and Moral Joy.

blurred text
blurred text
blurred text
blurred text